Cargando…
Analogy, explanation, and proof
People are habitual explanation generators. At its most mundane, our propensity to explain allows us to infer that we should not drink milk that smells sour; at the other extreme, it allows us to establish facts (e.g., theorems in mathematical logic) whose truth was not even known prior to the exist...
Autores principales: | , , |
---|---|
Formato: | Online Artículo Texto |
Lenguaje: | English |
Publicado: |
Frontiers Media S.A.
2014
|
Materias: | |
Acceso en línea: | https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4222223/ https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/25414655 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00867 |
_version_ | 1782342997077131264 |
---|---|
author | Hummel, John E. Licato, John Bringsjord, Selmer |
author_facet | Hummel, John E. Licato, John Bringsjord, Selmer |
author_sort | Hummel, John E. |
collection | PubMed |
description | People are habitual explanation generators. At its most mundane, our propensity to explain allows us to infer that we should not drink milk that smells sour; at the other extreme, it allows us to establish facts (e.g., theorems in mathematical logic) whose truth was not even known prior to the existence of the explanation (proof). What do the cognitive operations underlying the inference that the milk is sour have in common with the proof that, say, the square root of two is irrational? Our ability to generate explanations bears striking similarities to our ability to make analogies. Both reflect a capacity to generate inferences and generalizations that go beyond the featural similarities between a novel problem and familiar problems in terms of which the novel problem may be understood. However, a notable difference between analogy-making and explanation-generation is that the former is a process in which a single source situation is used to reason about a single target, whereas the latter often requires the reasoner to integrate multiple sources of knowledge. This seemingly small difference poses a challenge to the task of marshaling our understanding of analogical reasoning to understanding explanation. We describe a model of explanation, derived from a model of analogy, adapted to permit systematic violations of this one-to-one mapping constraint. Simulation results demonstrate that the resulting model can generate explanations for novel explananda and that, like the explanations generated by human reasoners, these explanations vary in their coherence. |
format | Online Article Text |
id | pubmed-4222223 |
institution | National Center for Biotechnology Information |
language | English |
publishDate | 2014 |
publisher | Frontiers Media S.A. |
record_format | MEDLINE/PubMed |
spelling | pubmed-42222232014-11-20 Analogy, explanation, and proof Hummel, John E. Licato, John Bringsjord, Selmer Front Hum Neurosci Neuroscience People are habitual explanation generators. At its most mundane, our propensity to explain allows us to infer that we should not drink milk that smells sour; at the other extreme, it allows us to establish facts (e.g., theorems in mathematical logic) whose truth was not even known prior to the existence of the explanation (proof). What do the cognitive operations underlying the inference that the milk is sour have in common with the proof that, say, the square root of two is irrational? Our ability to generate explanations bears striking similarities to our ability to make analogies. Both reflect a capacity to generate inferences and generalizations that go beyond the featural similarities between a novel problem and familiar problems in terms of which the novel problem may be understood. However, a notable difference between analogy-making and explanation-generation is that the former is a process in which a single source situation is used to reason about a single target, whereas the latter often requires the reasoner to integrate multiple sources of knowledge. This seemingly small difference poses a challenge to the task of marshaling our understanding of analogical reasoning to understanding explanation. We describe a model of explanation, derived from a model of analogy, adapted to permit systematic violations of this one-to-one mapping constraint. Simulation results demonstrate that the resulting model can generate explanations for novel explananda and that, like the explanations generated by human reasoners, these explanations vary in their coherence. Frontiers Media S.A. 2014-11-06 /pmc/articles/PMC4222223/ /pubmed/25414655 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00867 Text en Copyright © 2014 Hummel, Licato and Bringsjord. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms. |
spellingShingle | Neuroscience Hummel, John E. Licato, John Bringsjord, Selmer Analogy, explanation, and proof |
title | Analogy, explanation, and proof |
title_full | Analogy, explanation, and proof |
title_fullStr | Analogy, explanation, and proof |
title_full_unstemmed | Analogy, explanation, and proof |
title_short | Analogy, explanation, and proof |
title_sort | analogy, explanation, and proof |
topic | Neuroscience |
url | https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4222223/ https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/25414655 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00867 |
work_keys_str_mv | AT hummeljohne analogyexplanationandproof AT licatojohn analogyexplanationandproof AT bringsjordselmer analogyexplanationandproof |