Cargando…
Contexts as Shared Commitments
Contemporary semantics assumes two influential notions of context: one coming from Kaplan (1989), on which contexts are sets of predetermined parameters, and another originating in Stalnaker (1978), on which contexts are sets of propositions that are “common ground.” The latter is deservedly more po...
Autor principal: | |
---|---|
Formato: | Online Artículo Texto |
Lenguaje: | English |
Publicado: |
Frontiers Media S.A.
2015
|
Materias: | |
Acceso en línea: | https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4687163/ https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/26733087 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01932 |
_version_ | 1782406575892201472 |
---|---|
author | García-Carpintero, Manuel |
author_facet | García-Carpintero, Manuel |
author_sort | García-Carpintero, Manuel |
collection | PubMed |
description | Contemporary semantics assumes two influential notions of context: one coming from Kaplan (1989), on which contexts are sets of predetermined parameters, and another originating in Stalnaker (1978), on which contexts are sets of propositions that are “common ground.” The latter is deservedly more popular, given its flexibility in accounting for context-dependent aspects of language beyond manifest indexicals, such as epistemic modals, predicates of taste, and so on and so forth; in fact, properly dealing with demonstratives (perhaps ultimately all indexicals) requires that further flexibility. Even if we acknowledge Lewis (1980)'s point that, in a sense, Kaplanian contexts already include common ground contexts, it is better to be clear and explicit about what contexts constitutively are. Now, Stalnaker (1978, 2002, 2014) defines context-as-common-ground as a set of propositions, but recent work shows that this is not an accurate conception. The paper explains why, and provides an alternative. The main reason is that several phenomena (presuppositional treatments of pejoratives and predicates of taste, forces other than assertion) require that the common ground includes non-doxastic attitudes such as appraisals, emotions, etc. Hence the common ground should not be taken to include merely contents (propositions), but those together with attitudes concerning them: shared commitments, as I will defend. |
format | Online Article Text |
id | pubmed-4687163 |
institution | National Center for Biotechnology Information |
language | English |
publishDate | 2015 |
publisher | Frontiers Media S.A. |
record_format | MEDLINE/PubMed |
spelling | pubmed-46871632016-01-05 Contexts as Shared Commitments García-Carpintero, Manuel Front Psychol Psychology Contemporary semantics assumes two influential notions of context: one coming from Kaplan (1989), on which contexts are sets of predetermined parameters, and another originating in Stalnaker (1978), on which contexts are sets of propositions that are “common ground.” The latter is deservedly more popular, given its flexibility in accounting for context-dependent aspects of language beyond manifest indexicals, such as epistemic modals, predicates of taste, and so on and so forth; in fact, properly dealing with demonstratives (perhaps ultimately all indexicals) requires that further flexibility. Even if we acknowledge Lewis (1980)'s point that, in a sense, Kaplanian contexts already include common ground contexts, it is better to be clear and explicit about what contexts constitutively are. Now, Stalnaker (1978, 2002, 2014) defines context-as-common-ground as a set of propositions, but recent work shows that this is not an accurate conception. The paper explains why, and provides an alternative. The main reason is that several phenomena (presuppositional treatments of pejoratives and predicates of taste, forces other than assertion) require that the common ground includes non-doxastic attitudes such as appraisals, emotions, etc. Hence the common ground should not be taken to include merely contents (propositions), but those together with attitudes concerning them: shared commitments, as I will defend. Frontiers Media S.A. 2015-12-22 /pmc/articles/PMC4687163/ /pubmed/26733087 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01932 Text en Copyright © 2015 García-Carpintero. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms. |
spellingShingle | Psychology García-Carpintero, Manuel Contexts as Shared Commitments |
title | Contexts as Shared Commitments |
title_full | Contexts as Shared Commitments |
title_fullStr | Contexts as Shared Commitments |
title_full_unstemmed | Contexts as Shared Commitments |
title_short | Contexts as Shared Commitments |
title_sort | contexts as shared commitments |
topic | Psychology |
url | https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4687163/ https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/26733087 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01932 |
work_keys_str_mv | AT garciacarpinteromanuel contextsassharedcommitments |