Cargando…
Propensities and Second Order Uncertainty: A Modified Taxi Cab Problem
The study of people’s ability to engage in causal probabilistic reasoning has typically used fixed-point estimates for key figures. For example, in the classic taxi-cab problem, where a witness provides evidence on which of two cab companies (the more common ‘green’/less common ‘blue’) were responsi...
Autores principales: | , , , |
---|---|
Formato: | Online Artículo Texto |
Lenguaje: | English |
Publicado: |
Frontiers Media S.A.
2020
|
Materias: | |
Acceso en línea: | https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7607002/ https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/33192757 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.503233 |
_version_ | 1783604553372925952 |
---|---|
author | Dewitt, Stephen H. Fenton, Norman E. Liefgreen, Alice Lagnado, David A. |
author_facet | Dewitt, Stephen H. Fenton, Norman E. Liefgreen, Alice Lagnado, David A. |
author_sort | Dewitt, Stephen H. |
collection | PubMed |
description | The study of people’s ability to engage in causal probabilistic reasoning has typically used fixed-point estimates for key figures. For example, in the classic taxi-cab problem, where a witness provides evidence on which of two cab companies (the more common ‘green’/less common ‘blue’) were responsible for a hit and run incident, solvers are told the witness’s ability to judge cab color is 80%. In reality, there is likely to be some uncertainty around this estimate (perhaps we tested the witness and they were correct 4/5 times), known as second-order uncertainty, producing a distribution rather than a fixed probability. While generally more closely matching real world reasoning, a further important ramification of this is that our best estimate of the witness’ accuracy can and should change when the witness makes the claim that the cab was blue. We present a Bayesian Network model of this problem, and show that, while the witness’s report does increase our probability of the cab being blue, it simultaneously decreases our estimate of their future accuracy (because blue cabs are less common). We presented this version of the problem to 131 participants, requiring them to update their estimates of both the probability the cab involved was blue, as well as the witness’s accuracy, after they claim it was blue. We also required participants to explain their reasoning process and provided follow up questions to probe various aspects of their reasoning. While some participants responded normatively, the majority self-reported ‘assuming’ one of the probabilities was a certainty. Around a quarter assumed the cab was green, and thus the witness was wrong, decreasing their estimate of their accuracy. Another quarter assumed the witness was correct and actually increased their estimate of their accuracy, showing a circular logic similar to that seen in the confirmation bias/belief polarization literature. Around half of participants refused to make any change, with convergent evidence suggesting that these participants do not see the relevance of the witness’s report to their accuracy before we know for certain whether they are correct or incorrect. |
format | Online Article Text |
id | pubmed-7607002 |
institution | National Center for Biotechnology Information |
language | English |
publishDate | 2020 |
publisher | Frontiers Media S.A. |
record_format | MEDLINE/PubMed |
spelling | pubmed-76070022020-11-13 Propensities and Second Order Uncertainty: A Modified Taxi Cab Problem Dewitt, Stephen H. Fenton, Norman E. Liefgreen, Alice Lagnado, David A. Front Psychol Psychology The study of people’s ability to engage in causal probabilistic reasoning has typically used fixed-point estimates for key figures. For example, in the classic taxi-cab problem, where a witness provides evidence on which of two cab companies (the more common ‘green’/less common ‘blue’) were responsible for a hit and run incident, solvers are told the witness’s ability to judge cab color is 80%. In reality, there is likely to be some uncertainty around this estimate (perhaps we tested the witness and they were correct 4/5 times), known as second-order uncertainty, producing a distribution rather than a fixed probability. While generally more closely matching real world reasoning, a further important ramification of this is that our best estimate of the witness’ accuracy can and should change when the witness makes the claim that the cab was blue. We present a Bayesian Network model of this problem, and show that, while the witness’s report does increase our probability of the cab being blue, it simultaneously decreases our estimate of their future accuracy (because blue cabs are less common). We presented this version of the problem to 131 participants, requiring them to update their estimates of both the probability the cab involved was blue, as well as the witness’s accuracy, after they claim it was blue. We also required participants to explain their reasoning process and provided follow up questions to probe various aspects of their reasoning. While some participants responded normatively, the majority self-reported ‘assuming’ one of the probabilities was a certainty. Around a quarter assumed the cab was green, and thus the witness was wrong, decreasing their estimate of their accuracy. Another quarter assumed the witness was correct and actually increased their estimate of their accuracy, showing a circular logic similar to that seen in the confirmation bias/belief polarization literature. Around half of participants refused to make any change, with convergent evidence suggesting that these participants do not see the relevance of the witness’s report to their accuracy before we know for certain whether they are correct or incorrect. Frontiers Media S.A. 2020-10-20 /pmc/articles/PMC7607002/ /pubmed/33192757 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.503233 Text en Copyright © 2020 Dewitt, Fenton, Liefgreen and Lagnado. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms. |
spellingShingle | Psychology Dewitt, Stephen H. Fenton, Norman E. Liefgreen, Alice Lagnado, David A. Propensities and Second Order Uncertainty: A Modified Taxi Cab Problem |
title | Propensities and Second Order Uncertainty: A Modified Taxi Cab Problem |
title_full | Propensities and Second Order Uncertainty: A Modified Taxi Cab Problem |
title_fullStr | Propensities and Second Order Uncertainty: A Modified Taxi Cab Problem |
title_full_unstemmed | Propensities and Second Order Uncertainty: A Modified Taxi Cab Problem |
title_short | Propensities and Second Order Uncertainty: A Modified Taxi Cab Problem |
title_sort | propensities and second order uncertainty: a modified taxi cab problem |
topic | Psychology |
url | https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7607002/ https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/33192757 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.503233 |
work_keys_str_mv | AT dewittstephenh propensitiesandsecondorderuncertaintyamodifiedtaxicabproblem AT fentonnormane propensitiesandsecondorderuncertaintyamodifiedtaxicabproblem AT liefgreenalice propensitiesandsecondorderuncertaintyamodifiedtaxicabproblem AT lagnadodavida propensitiesandsecondorderuncertaintyamodifiedtaxicabproblem |