Cargando…

The fallacy of enrolling only high-risk subjects in cancer prevention trials: Is there a "free lunch"?

BACKGROUND: There is a common belief that most cancer prevention trials should be restricted to high-risk subjects in order to increase statistical power. This strategy is appropriate if the ultimate target population is subjects at the same high-risk. However if the target population is the general...

Descripción completa

Detalles Bibliográficos
Autores principales: Baker, Stuart G, Kramer, Barnett S, Corle, Donald
Formato: Texto
Lenguaje:English
Publicado: BioMed Central 2004
Materias:
Acceso en línea:https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC524373/
https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/15461821
http://dx.doi.org/10.1186/1471-2288-4-24
_version_ 1782121898471063552
author Baker, Stuart G
Kramer, Barnett S
Corle, Donald
author_facet Baker, Stuart G
Kramer, Barnett S
Corle, Donald
author_sort Baker, Stuart G
collection PubMed
description BACKGROUND: There is a common belief that most cancer prevention trials should be restricted to high-risk subjects in order to increase statistical power. This strategy is appropriate if the ultimate target population is subjects at the same high-risk. However if the target population is the general population, three assumptions may underlie the decision to enroll high-risk subject instead of average-risk subjects from the general population: higher statistical power for the same sample size, lower costs for the same power and type I error, and a correct ratio of benefits to harms. We critically investigate the plausibility of these assumptions. METHODS: We considered each assumption in the context of a simple example. We investigated statistical power for fixed sample size when the investigators assume that relative risk is invariant over risk group, but when, in reality, risk difference is invariant over risk groups. We investigated possible costs when a trial of high-risk subjects has the same power and type I error as a larger trial of average-risk subjects from the general population. We investigated the ratios of benefit to harms when extrapolating from high-risk to average-risk subjects. RESULTS: Appearances here are misleading. First, the increase in statistical power with a trial of high-risk subjects rather than the same number of average-risk subjects from the general population assumes that the relative risk is the same for high-risk and average-risk subjects. However, if the absolute risk difference rather than the relative risk were the same, the power can be less with the high-risk subjects. In the analysis of data from a cancer prevention trial, we found that invariance of absolute risk difference over risk groups was nearly as plausible as invariance of relative risk over risk groups. Therefore a priori assumptions of constant relative risk across risk groups are not robust, limiting extrapolation of estimates of benefit to the general population. Second, a trial of high-risk subjects may cost more than a larger trial of average risk subjects with the same power and type I error because of additional recruitment and diagnostic testing to identify high-risk subjects. Third, the ratio of benefits to harms may be more favorable in high-risk persons than in average-risk persons in the general population, which means that extrapolating this ratio to the general population would be misleading. Thus there is no free lunch when using a trial of high-risk subjects to extrapolate results to the general population. CONCLUSION: Unless the intervention is targeted to only high-risk subjects, cancer prevention trials should be implemented in the general population.
format Text
id pubmed-524373
institution National Center for Biotechnology Information
language English
publishDate 2004
publisher BioMed Central
record_format MEDLINE/PubMed
spelling pubmed-5243732004-10-29 The fallacy of enrolling only high-risk subjects in cancer prevention trials: Is there a "free lunch"? Baker, Stuart G Kramer, Barnett S Corle, Donald BMC Med Res Methodol Research Article BACKGROUND: There is a common belief that most cancer prevention trials should be restricted to high-risk subjects in order to increase statistical power. This strategy is appropriate if the ultimate target population is subjects at the same high-risk. However if the target population is the general population, three assumptions may underlie the decision to enroll high-risk subject instead of average-risk subjects from the general population: higher statistical power for the same sample size, lower costs for the same power and type I error, and a correct ratio of benefits to harms. We critically investigate the plausibility of these assumptions. METHODS: We considered each assumption in the context of a simple example. We investigated statistical power for fixed sample size when the investigators assume that relative risk is invariant over risk group, but when, in reality, risk difference is invariant over risk groups. We investigated possible costs when a trial of high-risk subjects has the same power and type I error as a larger trial of average-risk subjects from the general population. We investigated the ratios of benefit to harms when extrapolating from high-risk to average-risk subjects. RESULTS: Appearances here are misleading. First, the increase in statistical power with a trial of high-risk subjects rather than the same number of average-risk subjects from the general population assumes that the relative risk is the same for high-risk and average-risk subjects. However, if the absolute risk difference rather than the relative risk were the same, the power can be less with the high-risk subjects. In the analysis of data from a cancer prevention trial, we found that invariance of absolute risk difference over risk groups was nearly as plausible as invariance of relative risk over risk groups. Therefore a priori assumptions of constant relative risk across risk groups are not robust, limiting extrapolation of estimates of benefit to the general population. Second, a trial of high-risk subjects may cost more than a larger trial of average risk subjects with the same power and type I error because of additional recruitment and diagnostic testing to identify high-risk subjects. Third, the ratio of benefits to harms may be more favorable in high-risk persons than in average-risk persons in the general population, which means that extrapolating this ratio to the general population would be misleading. Thus there is no free lunch when using a trial of high-risk subjects to extrapolate results to the general population. CONCLUSION: Unless the intervention is targeted to only high-risk subjects, cancer prevention trials should be implemented in the general population. BioMed Central 2004-10-04 /pmc/articles/PMC524373/ /pubmed/15461821 http://dx.doi.org/10.1186/1471-2288-4-24 Text en Copyright © 2004 Baker et al; licensee BioMed Central Ltd. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0 This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License ( (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0) ), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
spellingShingle Research Article
Baker, Stuart G
Kramer, Barnett S
Corle, Donald
The fallacy of enrolling only high-risk subjects in cancer prevention trials: Is there a "free lunch"?
title The fallacy of enrolling only high-risk subjects in cancer prevention trials: Is there a "free lunch"?
title_full The fallacy of enrolling only high-risk subjects in cancer prevention trials: Is there a "free lunch"?
title_fullStr The fallacy of enrolling only high-risk subjects in cancer prevention trials: Is there a "free lunch"?
title_full_unstemmed The fallacy of enrolling only high-risk subjects in cancer prevention trials: Is there a "free lunch"?
title_short The fallacy of enrolling only high-risk subjects in cancer prevention trials: Is there a "free lunch"?
title_sort fallacy of enrolling only high-risk subjects in cancer prevention trials: is there a "free lunch"?
topic Research Article
url https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC524373/
https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/15461821
http://dx.doi.org/10.1186/1471-2288-4-24
work_keys_str_mv AT bakerstuartg thefallacyofenrollingonlyhighrisksubjectsincancerpreventiontrialsisthereafreelunch
AT kramerbarnetts thefallacyofenrollingonlyhighrisksubjectsincancerpreventiontrialsisthereafreelunch
AT corledonald thefallacyofenrollingonlyhighrisksubjectsincancerpreventiontrialsisthereafreelunch
AT bakerstuartg fallacyofenrollingonlyhighrisksubjectsincancerpreventiontrialsisthereafreelunch
AT kramerbarnetts fallacyofenrollingonlyhighrisksubjectsincancerpreventiontrialsisthereafreelunch
AT corledonald fallacyofenrollingonlyhighrisksubjectsincancerpreventiontrialsisthereafreelunch